Introduction
to the Self-Conscious Mind
Robert
G. Mays, BSc, and Suzanne B. Mays, AAS,
CMP
(updated
- 12/11/21)
For
a printable
version (PDF, 220K, 12 pages).
See also an earlier
introduction
(PDF, 85K, 7 pages, 2006).
Contents
Consciousness,
the brain and the “hard problem”
The
prevalent view in neuroscience is that the
brain produces
consciousness. We are conscious because the
electrical activity in our
brain's
neurons works in a complex way and
consciousness somehow “emerges” from
that
complex neural activity. The difficulty with
this view is that it
doesn't
really explain our interior, subjective experience
of consciousness, as
pointed out by David Chalmers (1996), which is
really the “hard
problem”
of consciousness.
Chalmers
argues that conscious experience can’t be
explained
solely from physical phenomena and offers
several arguments to support
this:
- The
brain’s neurological activity alone does not
explain the qualities
of our internal experience – why a red
object appears red
to us. A person brought up in a totally
black-and-white environment may
know everything there is to know about how
the brain produces color
experience but still would not know what it
is like to see color (the
qualia or knowledge argument).
- It
is logically conceivable that a physically
identical duplicate of a
person can exist which behaves identically
but which lacks conscious
experience. This possibility implies that
conscious experience is not
logically dependent (“supervenient”) on the
physical (the zombie
argument).
- It
is conceivable that in a world physically
identical to ours, conscious
experience is different,
for
example, that color experience is inverted –
where we see red, people
in the identical world see blue, and vice
versa (the inverted spectrum
argument).
- The
facts of physical causation in the world (in
physical objects,
biological systems, etc.) alone do not
suggest that there should be any
consciousness. The only way I know about
consciousness is because I
experience it (the epistemic asymmetry
argument).
- The
phenomenal “feel” of conscious experience
cannot be explained as a
functional property of a physical system
through functional analysis –
only the effects of
conscious
experience play functional roles (the
absence of analysis argument).
Chalmers
advocates the view that everything including
conscious
experience is a consequence of basic
properties and laws. Because
conscious
experience can’t be reduced to physical
processes, it necessarily
involves some
new fundamental properties and laws beyond the
existing physical laws.
The new laws
will be “psychophysical” laws which specify
how the phenomenal
properties of
consciousness depend on physical laws.
Chalmers calls this stance a
“naturalistic
dualism” in that consciousness can be
explained by basic natural laws,
not
through transcendent elements or mystery. But
the current natural laws
need to
be expanded.
Chalmers
rejects all forms of interactionist dualism,
which hold
that a non-physical consciousness could be
causally effective in
influencing
the brain. Even if a mechanism for causal
interaction could be found,
the
mechanism for interaction itself would not
explain conscious experience
any
more than neurological mechanisms do.
The
fundamental problem of a theory of
consciousness then is
bridging the “explanatory gap” between the
physical level and conscious
experience. Tim Bayne and Chalmers (2003)
further suggest that a theory
of
consciousness must be compatible with the idea
that a subject’s
conscious
states are necessarily unified, that is, the
conjunction of all of a
subject’s
phenomenal states at any time is itself a
phenomenal state. The notion
of the
unity of consciousness implies the concept of
a subject
in whom the phenomenal states are unified.
Consciousness
would then be viewed as a total phenomenal
state: what it is like to be
a
subject
at a time.
A
theory of
consciousness, mind and brain
In
earlier research (Mays & Mays, 2008a), we
introduced the
idea of the self-conscious mind*
or
simply
“mind”, an autonomous, non-material field of
consciousness, spatially
coextensive with the body which is intimately
integrated with the body
and
brain. The brain mediates cognitive faculties;
the brain’s neural
electrical
activity is required for consciousness. On the
basis of this model, we
propose
a theory of consciousness that addresses the
issues of the “hard
problem”. (*Our
concept of
the “self-conscious
mind” is different from that of Karl Popper
and John Eccles (1977) who
also
used the term in a dualist interactionist
theory of mind.)
A.
The
human
being consists of (1) an energetic,
spatially extended, non-material
“mind”
that is united with (2) a material brain and
body.
The mind is
a “field of consciousness”; it is non-material
(does not consist of
material
atoms, etc.) but rather is a structured,
energetic region of space that
can
interact with physical processes, in
particular with neurons, and thus
has
physical attributes. The mind is united and
co-extensive with the brain
and
body and interacts directly with the brain,
probably via electrical
interactions with cortical and other dendritic
structures. The
basic evidence for this idea derives
from the phenomena of the
near-death experience (NDE) (Moody, 1975;
Greyson, 2000) and various
neurological phenomena including phantom
limbs:
- The
mind is a separate entity, a “field of
consciousness”:
(1) During NDE, the locus of consciousness
appears to separate from the
physical body and operate independent of the
brain, having heightened,
lucid awareness, logical thought processes,
and vivid perceptions
including veridical perceptions of the
surroundings; (2) during the
out-of-body component of NDE, the locus of
consciousness has a
particular position in space and a
particular visual perspective; (3)
phantom limbs appear to be fields of
sensation extending beyond the
body in the space where the physical limb
was present, such that when
the phantom limb is “touched”, the amputee
can feel sensations and when
the phantom limb “touches” another person,
that person experiences
sensations (Mays & Mays, 2008b); (4)
amputees generally can
feel “touch” during Therapeutic Touch
therapy of their phantom and the
therapist can generally “feel” the presence
of the phantom limb
(Leskowitz, 2000 and 2001).
- The
mind is non-material, but has the
character of a structured energy
field, interacts with physical processes,
and thus has physical
attributes:
(1) The out-of-body mind appears to pass
readily through solid objects
and is invisible to ordinary sight, but it
also appears to interact in
subtle ways with physical processes:
physical objects, light, sound,
and other persons’ bodies; (2) the
out-of-body mind entity can
apparently be “seen” by animals; (3) phantom
limb “touch” on another
person’s head in the region of the brain can
elicit visual and other
sensations similar to electrical brain
stimulation (Mays &
Mays, 2008b); (4) at least two phantom limb
subjects (M.G. and A.Z.)
report being able to “see” their phantom
limbs as a faint glow against
a dark background or in the dark (Mays &
Mays, unpublished
report, 2009; Brugger, et al., 2000); (5) a
field (region of space)
which entails interaction with physical
processes, itself has physical
attributes, although it is not like any
currently known physical fields.
- The
mind is united with the brain and
interacts directly with it, probably
via electrical interactions:
(1) People generally feel that their locus
of consciousness extends
throughout their physical body; (2)
electrical brain activity is
correlated with conscious experiences (e.g.,
electrical brain
stimulation, EEG, brain imaging
technologies); (3) some NDE accounts
include a report of the NDEr “merging” with
an in-body person in order
to see and hear through them (Mays &
Mays, 2008a); (4) some
NDEs suggest an electrical nature to the
NDEr’s “body” (e.g.,
interaction with fog); (5) one after-effect
of NDE is abnormally high
electrostatic charges around the person's
body, which can interfere
with watches and electronic equipment.
B.
The
mind is the seat of conscious experience.
All cognitive faculties (perception, thinking,
feelings, volition, memory and self-awareness)
reside in the
non-material mind
entity, not in the brain. However, the mind
ordinarily is completely
dependent
on brain structures and neural activity for
consciousness. Mental
events become
conscious only when there is sufficient
electrical brain activity. If
the
electrical activity is not sufficient, the
percept or other mental
event
remains subliminal. On the other hand, the
mind can initiate electrical
brain
activity and thereby serves as
the agent that initiates volitional activity,
exerts “mental
force”, alters brain neural patterns
plastically, and is the unified
phenomenal
field resulting in the sense of the unity of
consciousness.
- All
cognitive faculties reside in the
non-material mind, but ordinarily
need the brain’s neural activity for
conscious awareness:
(1) During NDE, the locus of consciousness
retains all cognitive
faculties while apparently operating
independent of the brain; (2) in
the ordinary case, if a person loses brain
electrical activity, they
become unconscious.
- Consciousness
requires
sufficient electrical brain activity, else
sensations remain
subliminal:
(1) Sensations become conscious only after a
sufficient duration of
electrical brain activity (Libet, 1973;
Libet, et al., 1975; Libet, et
al., 1991); (2) lower than liminal stimuli
do not rise to conscious
awareness but forced-choice responses are
accurate (e.g., Libet, 2004,
cases of blindsight, etc.).
- A
mental agent appears to initiate
electrical brain activity:
(1) People generally sense that “their”
volitional activity results in
their physical movement, speech acts, etc.;
(2) cognitive behavioral
therapy for obsessive-compulsive disorder
implies an agent that
generates a “mental force” which causes
neural changes (Schwartz,
1999); (3) “plastic”
changes in neural structures can occur
rapidly when fine motor
movements are practiced mentally (e.g.,
Pascual-Leone, et al., 1995),
which implies an agent that exerts purely
endogenous mental effort can
effect neural reorganization and physical
performance improvement.
- A
mental agency appears to serve as the
unified phenomenal field:
(1) Subjective backward referral of
sensation, in which a person
appears to “antedate” the time and specific
body location of a stimulus
even though awareness of the sensation comes
500 msec later (Libet,
1973; Libet, et al., 1975), implies an
agency that “holds together” the
time and location until the sensation comes
to consciousness; (2)
large-scale phase-locked neural synchrony
occurs cross-hemispherically
from posterior to anterior brain regions
during arousal, sensorimotor
integration, attentional selection,
perception and working memory (Lutz
and Thompson, 2003), and implies an agency
that effects the synchrony
and produces the subject’s unified
phenomenal experience.
C.
When
brain
structures are damaged, mental faculties
dependent on them are
partially
or totally impaired.
For example, memory content resides solely in
the mind entity but
memory formation, consolidation and recall
require hippocampal and
other
structures, and when the latter are damaged,
memory function is
impaired.
Impairment is due to interference with the
interface between the
neurons and the
corresponding structures of the mind. The
field of the mind has an
internal
structure which corresponds to the cortical
and other neural structures
of the
brain. In fact, it is likely that the internal
structure of the mind’s
field
directly maps to the neural structure
throughout the body. The mind
depends on
brain neural activity in particular cortical
locations for particular
cognitive activities.
- Brain
damage causes mental impairment, by
interfering with the neural
interface to the mind:
(1) There are numerous examples connecting
brain damage to cognitive
impairment, in addition to memory
impairments; (2) damage to neurons
implies that the neural interface to the
mind is impaired such that
sensory, motor, affective and thought
processes may be altered or
impaired; (3) during anesthesia, the
anesthetic agent suffuses the
brain and the patient loses consciousness,
implying that the anesthetic
agent interferes with the neural interface
with the mind.
- Field
of the mind has an internal structure:
(1) In at least some NDErs, the out-of-body
“body” appears to have an
intricate, luminous structure, for example
with tiny structures in the
hands and tubes of light up the arms (Moody
& Perry, 1988, p.
10); (2) (from a previous point) the
interaction of the mind with the
body is probably via electrical interactions
with neurons; (3) in order
to selectively interact with specific neural
activity, the mind needs
to be in close proximity with specific
neurons; (4) some NDE accounts
include a report of the NDEr “merging” with
an in-body person in order
to see and hear through them (Mays &
Mays, 2008a), which
implies
that the mind’s internal structure can
interface with the brain in a
similar way from one person to another and
therefore the mind’s
internal structure is similar from person to
person; (5) there is an
unusual
relationship between phantom limb sensations
and neural activity in the
stump, implying a connection between stump
neurons and mind structures
in the phantom: sensations can be modulated
by stump manipulations,
temporarily abolished by local stump
anesthesia, or altered by changes
in stump blood flow, and altering the sodium
channel conductance in
stump neurons can increase or block phantom
limb pain (Nikolajsen
& Jensen, 2001).
- Interaction
of the mind’s field with the brain occurs
in particular cortical
locations:
Brodmann areas have distinctive
cytoarchitectures (Brodmann, 1909),
which generally map to cognitive functional
areas, and other structural
differences exist between functional areas,
which implies that
particular mind structures interact with
particular cortical and other
neural structures in the brain.
D.
This
theory
solves the “hard problem” of how conscious
experience can arise
from
physical brain activity
– conscious experience depends on a second
entity
with physical attributes, the conscious mind,
which interacts with the
brain to
produce phenomenal experience. Subjective
experiences of qualia are an
effect
in the mind resulting from neural electrical
activity in specific
regions of
the brain. A philosophical zombie duplicate of
a person is impossible
because a
physical duplicate would necessarily include a
conscious mind as well
as a
physical body and thus would entail conscious
experience. The unity of
consciousness results from the unity of the
mind’s “field of
consciousness”.
The mind is the subject in
whom
phenomenal states are unified.
- The
conscious mind, a second entity with
physical attributes, interacts
with the brain:
(earlier points) (1) The mind is a separate
entity, a “field of
consciousness”; (2) the mind is non-material
but interacts with
physical processes and thus has physical
attributes; (3) the mind is
united with the brain and interacts directly
with it, probably via
electrical interactions; (4) all cognitive
faculties reside in the
non-material mind
- Interaction
with the brain produces phenomenal
experience:
(1) There are at least five situations in
which phenomenal experience
occurs: (a) during NDE, the out-of-body
person has phenomenal
experience by apparent direct interaction
with physical processes
(light, sound, etc.) without apparent
involvement from the brain or
body, implying that the brain and body are
not necessary for phenomenal
experience; (b) a limb deficient person has
phenomenal experience by
apparent “touch” of the phantom limb by an
object or another person
(Mays & Mays, 2008b; Leskowitz, 2000 and
2001), implying that
phenomenal experience can occur with
interaction by physical processes
with the non-material field of the phantom;
(c) a person has phenomenal
experience by apparent “touch” in the brain
region by another person’s
phantom limb (Mays & Mays, 2008b),
implying that the phantom
limb can induce phenomenal experience in
another person through
interaction with the brain; (d) a person has
phenomenal experience by
direct cortical electrical stimulation
(Penfield & Rasmussen,
1950), implying that electrical brain
activity imposed from without can
produce phenomenal experience; (e) a person
has phenomenal experience
by ordinary sensory stimuli, implying that
phenomenal experience occurs
in this case by the electrical brain
activity interacting with the
mind’s field. (2) Thus, interaction of the
field of the mind in a
variety of ways always entails phenomenal
experience, including
interaction of the mind with the brain.
- Experiences
of qualia are an effect in the mind
resulting from electrical activity
in specific regions:
(1) (previous point) Interaction with the
brain produces phenomenal
experience; (2) (previous point) interaction
of the mind’s field with
the brain occurs in particular cortical
locations; (3) particular
cortical locations are associated with
phenomenal experience of
particular qualia, which implies that
electrical activity in a
particular location affects the mind’s field
in that location and
produces that specific associated quale.
- A
philosophical zombie duplicate of a person
is impossible:
(1) (previous point) The mind is
non-material but interacts with
physical processes and thus has physical
attributes; (2) a physical
duplicate would necessarily include a
conscious mind as well as a
physical body; (3) (previous point) all
cognitive faculties reside in
the mind, but ordinarily need the brain’s
neural activity for conscious
awareness, implying that the duplicate would
have phenomenal
experiences.
- The
unity of consciousness results from the
unity of the mind’s “field of
consciousness”:
(1) During NDE, the locus of consciousness
appears to be in a single
location with a particular visual
perspective; (2) during NDE, the
out-of-body “body” appears to be a single
field which is never divided,
implying that the mind’s “field of
consciousness” is a singular entity.
- Phenomenal
states are unified in the mind as subject:
During NDE, the mind “field of
consciousness” is the locus of all
phenomenal states and is felt to be the
person’s self.
E.
All
interactions
in the mind have two sides: they entail both
phenomenal
experience and a physical
causal
role.
Physical
causal closure is maintained because the mind
is a non-material entity
with
physical attributes, whose structures can act
causally on neural
processes. The
domain of what constitutes “the physical” must
necessarily be expanded.
The
conscious mind entails new fundamental
properties and is a fundamental
aspect
of reality, namely a person’s seat of
consciousness.
- Interactions
in the mind always entail phenomenal
experience:
(1) (previous point) There are at least five
situations in which
phenomenal experience occurs: (a) during
NDE, (b) “touch” of a phantom
limb region, (c) “touch” of the brain region
of a subject by a phantom
limb, (d) electrical brain stimulation, and
(e) ordinary sensory
stimuli, each involving interactions with
the mind; (2) there are no
known interactions with the mind which do
not entail phenomenal
experience.
- Interactions
in the mind always entail a physical
causal role:
(1) (previous point) The five situations
involving interaction with the
mind include a physical causal role by (a)
direct physical processes
(light, sound, objects), (b) direct physical
processes (objects or
another person), (c) the brain of the second
subject, (d) electrical
pulses to the patient’s brain, and (e)
physical stimuli acting on
sensory neurons; (2) there are no known
interactions with the mind
which do not entail a physical causal role,
except possibly telepathy,
which may still require neural activity to
be received.
- Causal
closure of the physical is maintained:
(1) (previous point) The mind interacts with
physical processes, and
thus has physical attributes, implying that
at some level, the field of
the mind becomes a physically causal entity.
- The
domain of “the physical” must necessarily
be expanded:
When phenomena are discovered which imply
new physical entities or
forces, the domain of what constitutes
physical reality has
historically been expanded. The case of the
mind as a new aspect of
reality is no different.
- The
mind is a fundamental aspect of reality
with new properties and is a
person’s seat of consciousness:
(1) conscious experience is a fundamental
aspect of human beings and
(we can infer) some animals; (2) (previous
point) the mind is
non-material, but has the character of a
structured energy field and
interacts with physical processes, implying
that it has properties that
are unique; (3) (previous point) all
cognitive faculties reside in the
non-material mind, implying that the mind is
the seat of the person’s
consciousness.
Objections
to dualism
The
present theory is a form of
“interactionist dualism”, which posits the
mind and the body, and a
mechanism
for the interaction between them. The
main
objections to dualism, and responses
relating to this
theory, are:
- How
can
mind-brain interaction occur?
There
is no conceivable mechanism whereby a
totally non-physical mind could
affect the
material body. If the mind and body are
totally different types of
things, how
can they intermingle and interact with each
other? Response:
The mind is not totally non-physical. It
is
non-material, but has the character of a
structured energy field that
interacts
with physical processes. The evidence
supporting this view, presented
earlier,
includes phenomena from NDEs and from
phantom limb interactions. In
addition,
see the following section on “Interaction of
the non-material mind with
physical processes”.
- How
does
brain injury also impair the non-physical
mind?
When the brain is damaged in some way,
mental faculties are always
compromised or impaired to some degree. If
the mind is a completely
separate
substance from the brain, how does brain
injury also impair the mind?
(Churchland, 1988). Response:
The
mind is not a completely separate substance
from the brain. It
has the
character of a structured energy field that
interacts with physical
processes,
in particular with neurons. Impairment is
due to interference with the
interface between the neurons and the
corresponding structures of the
mind.
- How
can
the
mechanism for interaction between the
brain and mind explain phenomenal
experience?
Even if a mechanism for causal interaction
could be found, the
mechanism for interaction itself would not
explain conscious experience
any
more than neurological mechanisms do
(Chalmers, 1996).
Response:
The mind is itself the locus of phenomenal
experience. All interactions with the mind
entail phenomenal
experience. The
evidence supporting this view, presented
earlier, includes phenomena
from NDEs
and from phantom limb interactions.
- How
does
this
view avoid the Cartesian Theater in the
brain?
An
interactionist dualist theory posits that
the brain informs the mind of
perceptions and the mind directs the brain
in appropriate action. The
mind is
thus like a “homunculus” in the brain. There
is no interior homunculus
observing the results of neural activity and
giving commands in a
“Cartesian Theater
in the brain”, as such theories imply
(Dennett, 1991). Response: The mind’s
structures unite
directly with neural structures without an
intermediate stage of
“interpretation”. All neural activity
interacts directly with the mind,
resulting in phenomenal experience. Even
stimuli of very short duration
result
in phenomenal experience, albeit subliminal.
- How
is
this
view not a category-mistake? How is this
not just a “ghost in the
machine”?
A theory
that places “mind” and “body” together in
relation to one another as
terms of
the same logical category makes a
category-mistake, since they are not
of the
same logical category. There is no hidden
entity, the “mind”, inside a
mechanical “body” (Ryle, 1949). Response:
Both the mind and the material body are
objective, spatially
extended entities, one a non-material field
and the other a material
object, which
unite together to form a cohesive unity.
There is no category-mistake
of
relating entities belonging to different
logical categories: both mind
and body
are objective aspects of reality that relate
to each other through
physical
interaction. There is no “ghost in the
machine” because the mind is
closely
united with the body through a physical
interaction relationship.
- Doesn’t
this
view violate causal closure of the
physical?
Causal interactions between a non-physical
entity and a material body
would violate the “causal closure of the
physical world”. The
interaction of a
non-physical entity would introduce an
influence on a physical system
which
would violate the principle that all
physical effects can be ultimately
reduced
to physical causes. Response:
The
mind is
a field (region of space) that interacts
with physical processes, and
thus has
physical attributes, implying that at some
level, the field of the mind
acts as
a physically causal entity. As a
consequence, the domain of what
constitutes
“the physical” must necessarily be expanded
to include minds. Causal
closure of the physical world is
maintained.
Aren’t
NDEs just the result of abnormal brain
function?
A
number of physiological factors are
generally cited as explanations of NDE
(Greyson, et al., 2009). None of
these
explanations is adequate to explain NDE,
because (1) the reported
experiences
bear only slight resemblance to NDE, (2) many
NDEs occur under
conditions
without the suggested physiological factor, or
(3) in cases where the
physiological
factor is present, NDEs are not reported in
even a large percent of
cases.
- Altered blood gas
levels:
Cerebral hypoxia or anoxia (too little or no
oxygen), especially in
cases of induced rapid acceleration (G-force
loss of consciousness),
and hypercarbia (elevated carbon dioxide)
are cited as factors
resulting in NDE-like experiences. While
hypoxic conditions do
sometimes involve NDE features (tunnel
vision, bright lights, sense of
floating, brief fragmented visual images),
their primary features
include symptoms not found in NDEs – jerking
movements, compromised
memory, tingling sensations, confusion upon
wakening, etc. Similarly,
while hypercarbic conditions apparently
produce some features commonly
found in NDEs, these features are rare and
other NDE features are
absent. Furthermore, NDEs occur in
conditions without hypoxia or anoxia
(non-life-threatening illnesses, falls,
etc.) and NDEs occur in
patients where measured blood levels do not
reflect lowered oxygen or
elevated carbon dioxide levels. Finally,
NDEs occur in only 10-20% of
cardiac arrest cases where anoxic conditions
are very likely to occur.
- Neurochemical
factors:
Release of endorphins or similar chemicals
in the brain at the time of
stress may produce cessation of pain and
feelings of peace, both common
in NDEs. However, injection of endorphins
tends to produce long-lasting
effects, whereas these effects in NDEs begin
and end abruptly, with
separation from and return to the body. An
endogenous ketamine-like
anesthetic agent may produce effects similar
to low doses of ketamine
(sense of being out of the body, travel
through a tunnel to a light,
believing one has died, etc.) However,
unlike the vast majority of
NDEs, ketamine experiences are usually
frightening, having bizarre
imagery and are felt to be illusory. Other
important features of NDEs
(meeting deceased friends and relatives,
life review) are absent from
reported ketamine experiences.
- Temporal lobe
seizure or other
abnormal electrical activity in specific
brain regions:
Abnormal electrical activity or dysfunction
in the temporal lobes are
claimed to produce all or most NDE phenomena
(out-of-body sensations,
panoramic memories, mystical visions, vivid
hallucinations, etc.).
Electrical brain stimulation studies by
Wilder Penfield are commonly
cited as evidence. However, electrical brain
stimulation is not the
same as seizure or dysfunctional electrical
activity in the temporal
lobe and the experiences cited are
dissimilar to those reported in NDEs
(fragments of music, isolated scenes from
memory, fear or other
negative emotions, bizarre imagery, etc.)
Transcranial magnetic
stimulation (TMS) has also been cited as
inducing all of the major
components of NDE (out-of-body experiences,
being pulled toward a
light, hearing strange music, etc.).
However, the experiences reported
were unlike typical NDE features or were too
vague to compare, and
other researchers were unable to replicate
the results. Finally,
temporal lobe seizures themselves do not
result in experiences that
resemble NDE features.
- Induced
out-of-body experiences
(OBEs):
Out-of-body experiences have been claimed to
result from seizure
activity or electrical stimulation in the
region of the
temporo-parietal junction (TPJ), which is
thought to involve
integration of vestibular information with
other sensory information
regarding the location of the body in
perceptual space (Blanke, et al.,
2002 and 2004). The interpretation of the
results of these studies,
involving a total of six patients, is
controversial. In one patient no
overt anatomical defect or specific
diagnosis could be identified, so
identifying even general localization is
completely speculative for
this case. Further, there is no clear
evidence of lateralization, for
example to the right TPJ, because the
remaining cases are split between
the right (n=2) and left hemispheres (n=3).
The generalization of cases
of moderate to severe neurological pathology
to all
persons experiencing OBE is conjectural when
such pathology is
apparently absent in the vast majority of
persons experiencing OBE.
Further, the cases of OBE associated with
TPJ seizure and electrical
stimulation are not typical of spontaneous
OBEs, especially those
associated with NDE: TPJ induced OBEs are
more fragmentary, distorted
and illusory, involving incomplete or
non-veridical elements. (Veridical
in this sense includes both the patient’s
subjective sense of being
real and verification that what was
observed had
actually occurred.) In spontaneous OBEs,
there is a strong sense of the
reality of the experience, body image
disturbances are unusual,
veridical perception of events, including
those occurring at a
distance, are present in many cases, and
non-veridical perceptions are
rare.
While
none of these
physiological factors is adequate to explain
NDE, such factors may play
a role,
for example in triggering the onset of NDE.
The similarities which are
observed
may be an indication of this role. However, no
single physiological
factor is
present in all cases of NDE: the NDE appears
to be a phenomenon with
multiple possible
triggers.
Interaction
of the non-material mind with physical
processes
How
does the non-material mind interact with the
physical processes of
the brain and body?
The NDE “body” appears to be
non-material: it readily passes through solid
objects, cannot be seen
or heard,
etc., and has no apparent interaction with
physical processes. However,
the NDE
literature includes a number of reports of
NDErs interacting with
physical
processes. The interactions are subtle
but do
occur. Furthermore, a
phantom limb appears to be a “field of
sensation and touch”, where the
physical
limb once was, and also exhibits subtle
interactions with physical
processes.
Evidence
of interaction from NDEs:
In
NDE, the NDEr’s “body” appears to be a thing
(a field) with a shape and
location (Mays & Mays, 2008a). The “body”
may appear luminous
to the NDEr,
with a luminous interior structure, and can be
“seen” by animals and
fellow
NDErs. There is apparent interaction with
physical processes such as
light and
sound, because the NDEr reports veridical
visual and auditory
perceptions.
There is apparent interaction with physical
objects, because the NDEr
can bob
on the ceiling, and feels slight resistance
when passing through
objects such
as walls. There is one account of an NDE
involving apparent interaction
of the
NDEr’s “body” with fog on a cold night. The
NDEr jumped up and down and
the
“jumping fog” was seen by another man.
The
NDEr “body” can interact with
another person's body: an NDEr’s hand went
through the doctor’s arm,
which felt
“gelatinous”; an NDEr could tickle the nose of
another patient until
she
sneezed. There are at least three cases where
an NDEr “merged” with
another
person to see and feel what they were seeing,
feeling and thinking.
These cases
imply that interaction with and influence over
neural activity in the
brain is
possible, in particular, “merging” implies
that the mind readily joins
with and
interacts with the brain, even another
person’s brain.
Evidence
of interaction from phantom limbs:
A phantom limb is the vivid subjective
experience of the presence of
a limb that is absent congenitally or through
amputation. The phantom
limb also
appears to have objective reality as a “field
of sensation and touch”
in the
region where the physical limb was (Mays &
Mays, 2008b).
Phantom limbs appear
to be the exposed “mind limbs” extending
beyond the physical body.
We
have observed interactions with one
subject (M.G.), born without the fingers of
her left hand. Her phantom
fingers
“touching” physical objects evokes
physiological sensations in the
finger buds,
in the left palm and along the left arm, and
presents physiological
reactions (increased
skin color, twitching of the finger buds). In
experiments “touching” a
number
of other subjects, especially in the region of
the brain, the “touch”
evokes
subtle but definite physiological sensations
(warmth, pressure in the
head and
sinuses) and distinct, unusual inner visual
images. M.G. also reports
that
“massage” of her phantom fingers (i.e., the
therapist passing her hand
over the
finger area) evokes tickling sensations.
Finally, M.G. reports that she
sometimes can “see” her phantom fingers as a
faint whitish or bluish
light when
held up against a dark background. (Another
congenitally limb deficient
subject, A.Z., reports similar ability: “In
darkness, I have noted a
faint
glowing of my phantom body parts”, in Brugger,
et al., 2000.)
A
number of case reports appear in the
literature (e.g., Leskowitz, 2000 and 2001;
Sheldrake, 1995, pp.
152-153)
involving Therapeutic Touch treatment of
amputee phantom limb pain. The
common
features of these cases include: (1) the
therapist can usually feel the
phantom
limb as “present” in the expected location,
sometimes having a
distinctive
“energy”; (2) the patient can usually feel the
presence of the
therapist’s hand
in the phantom limb area that the therapist is
working in, despite the
fact
that the patient cannot see what the therapist
is doing (the eyes are
closed,
the patient is looking away or the patient’s
eyes are bandaged); and
(3) the
patient experiences immediate and dramatic
reduction in the subjective
pain; the
pain reduction is usually long-lasting after
several sessions.
Evidence
from both NDE and phantom limb phenomena
thus suggest that
interaction occurs
between the non-material field of the
person and physical processes (objects, light,
fog and sound), as well
as another
person. The interactions evoke phenomenal
sensations in the subject and
in the
other person. In addition, evidence also
suggests that the non-material
field
can appear luminous at times, both to the
subject and to animals.
Implications
of this theory
There
is
a process of “coming to awareness”:
Benjamin Libet’s “time-on” principle (Libet,
et al., 1991) proposes
that about ½ sec (500 msec) of brain
electrical activity is required
before a
person becomes aware of a sensation,
regardless of its content. The
person
adjusts for this delay by “antedating” the
subjective sensations back
to their
actual time. For example, a person can process
and react to an
emergency before
becoming conscious of it (Libet, 2004). In
Libet’s view, sensations are
first
subliminal. Visual stimuli that are presented
too quickly for conscious
awareness are nevertheless “seen” and
“interpreted” if the subject is
forced to
give an answer. Subjects show greater accuracy
for longer presentation
times. A
person can be (emotionally) affected when
shown an emotionally
evocative
picture, even if the perception remains
subliminal. These cases imply
that there
is subliminal cognitive processing (detection,
recognition) which
occurs prior
to awareness. We propose that all
conscious experience requires at least 500
msec of brain electrical
activity to
come to consciousness, including endogenous
mental acts such as
thoughts,
images and decisions. This proposition is
similar to Libet’s own
proposal
(1993, p. 385). The thought, image or decision
remains subliminal for
the
time-on period but is not
antedated
to its time origin.
Libet’s
delayed
awareness of willed action:
In a series of experiments to time the
relationship between the
subjective sense of willing to move and the
actual movement, Libet told
subjects to flex their wrists at a time freely
chosen (Libet, 1985;
Libet, et
al., 1983). The neural response to a
subjective command to move is
measured at
the top of the head and is called a “readiness
potential”, a slow rise
in
electrical negativity which indicates
preparation for the movement.
In
these experiments, Libet found that
the readiness potential neural response (RP)
typically started 550 msec
before
the actual muscle movement measured at the
wrist by an electromyogram
(EMG). Libet
asked subjects to note the time they first
became aware of wanting to
move, by noting the position
of a revolving spot on a
circular electronic “clock”. Ironically, the
subject’s first
awareness of the intention or wish to move
(W) was on average
about 350 msec after the
onset of
the
readiness potential. This delay makes it
appear that the brain has
decided to
move prior to the subject’s
actual
conscious intention to move.
The
apparent “decision” by the brain to
act prior to the actual awareness of the
intention to act is
counterintuitive
and implies that people do not act out of free
will, even when they
subjectively feel that they do. However, if
one accepts the proposition
that
people’s awareness of their own endogenous
mental acts is delayed (see
previous
section), Libet’s result is less enigmatic. We
propose that the
initially
subliminal wish to move requires a time-on of
about 500 msec before the
awareness
of the wish to move (W) and, thus, occurs some
150 msec prior to the
onset of
the readiness potential. The relative times of
events from Libet’s
experiments
would thus be as follows:
- -700
msec: wish to move, initially subliminal
(proposed)
- -550
msec: readiness potential begins (RP)
- -200
msec: awareness of wish to move (W)
- - 85
msec:
awareness of
moving (M)
-
0
msec: muscle movement (EMG)
How
can people subconsciously intend to
do something and then a half second later
become aware of the
intention? In our
view, a freewill decision originates in the
conscious agency of the
self-conscious mind, but the neural activity
reflecting this mental act
must
meet the 500-msec time-on requirement before
there can be awareness of
the
decision. This explanation is consistent with
people’s subjective
experience
that their decisions are purely their own and
arise from the conscious
context
they are in: They would be very surprised to
find that they have
decided
something contrary to that context.
The
time-on delay of awareness of
endogenous mental acts thus helps explain the
apparent disconnect
between
volition and action in this experiment, and in
other cases such as
William James’s
(1890) introspection of the process of getting
out of bed on a freezing
morning. Libet’s counterintuitive result
points to the unusual way we
are
organized: a non-material mind interfacing
through the relatively slow
electrical activity of the brain.
The
mind
plays an active role in brain development:
In postnatal brain development, significant
“regressive events” occur
during infancy in which many neurons die off,
and there is gradual
“myelination” of other neurons. Myelin is an
electrically insulating
sheath
that covers the axon so the neuron can
efficiently transfer neural
impulses. The
first brain areas to be myelinated are the
motor, olfactory, and
somatosensory
areas. The last areas, myelinated, in teen and
early adult years, are
complex
visual functions, executive functions, and
working memory. We propose
that the
mind’s activity of interfacing with neural
electrical activity,
especially
during infancy and early childhood, influences
which neurons are
retained and
myelinated, and thus become available for use.
This view has
implications for
child development and education. Child
development entails the child’s
mind
integrating with and re-forming the brain and
body through its own
activity.
Educational programs should thus be formulated
in attunement with the
child’s
and teen’s brain development, and use
age-appropriate mental and
physical
activities to enhance mind, brain and physical
development at each
developmental stage.
Memory
resides
in the mind, not in the brain:
Brain structures and pathways, especially in
the hippocampus, are
needed to form, consolidate and recall
memories. Bilateral damage to
the
hippocampus results in the inability to form
new memories (anterograde
amnesia).
In contrast, memories that are formed during
NDE are accessible
afterward. They
generally are vivid, long-lasting and not
subject to embellishment over
time.
This result implies that memories can be
formed and “stored” without
the brain.
Moreover, memories prior to NDE are accessible
during NDE, which
implies that
memory content is accessible without the
brain.
The
results of NDE accounts imply that
memory formation and recall are both functions
of the mind and are only
supported
by brain functions while in the body. In
addition, memory content
resides in
the mind, not the brain, which suggests that
profound retrograde
amnesia (loss
of long-term memory), such as in dementia, is
probably due to the
destruction
of brain structures that mediate memory recall
rather than destruction
of
memory content itself. In
this
view,
existing memories are not destroyed in
dementia patients with the
deterioration
of cortical structures and would return with
even a slight reversal of
certain cortical
deterioration. Rather than lose
the
past, people with Alzheimer’s disease
gradually become blind
to it.
Just
what is the self-conscious mind?
What
is the self-conscious mind exactly? Is it
“transcendent” or
mystical? In
our research, we rely on the
phenomena to define the boundaries and extent
of the theory. We prefer
not to
speculate beyond what the phenomena indicate.
The
mind presents itself as a field,
that is, a region of space with specific
properties. The essential
property of
the mind is consciousness, more precisely the
conscious experience of a
particular individual. The mind has
energetic
attributes in that it
appears to interact with physical processes,
especially with neurons,
and
appears to exhibit electrical effects and
luminosity. The mind appears
to have
a complex internal structure that
probably directly maps to the neural
structure throughout the brain and body.
There
are
three modes in which the mind can be
conscious: (1) during
ordinary consciousness, the mind is united
with the physical body and
is conscious because of interactions with
the brain and body; (2)
during NDE, the mind is separated from the
physical body and is
conscious because of direct interactions
with physical processes, such
as light and sound; and (3) in a phantom
limb, a portion of the mind’s
field is exposed as a kind of “mind limb” –
the region where the
physical limb was present – and the person
can sometimes experience
conscious sensations of “touch” when an
object or another
person’s body interacts with the mind limb
field.
Is
the mind a kind of subtle substance? The
self-conscious mind does not appear to have
properties of a
substance, in particular because it appears to
be unitary and
indivisible, although
it has extension and location in space. The
mind readily
interpenetrates
ordinary matter and, thus, is not material in
any ordinary sense.
Rather than a
subtle substance, the mind appears to be more
the seat of consciousness
and the
essential selfhood of the person.
Can
the non-material mind be studied
scientifically?
What the mind is and how it functions with the
brain are ultimately
empirical questions. Objective, non-material
entities can be studied
scientifically
through their effects on other entities. We
propose that further
scientific
investigation can be profitable in the
following areas:
- Phantom
limb phenomena:
The phantom limb provides direct access to a
“mind limb”, its inherent
internal structure and how that structure
interacts with the body and
brain, in particular with the neurons in the
stump. The phenomenal
experience of phantom limb sensations and
phantom limb pain are
directly reportable, as are interactions of
the phantom limb field with
other subjects. Direct physical interaction
of the limb field in
measurement devices may also be possible.
Research in this area also
has the potential to develop effective
treatment modalities for phantom
limb pain, which has hitherto proved
intractable.
- NDE
phenomena:
More thorough surveys of NDE accounts should
provide additional cases
and data about interactions with physical
processes and “merging” of
the NDEr with in-body persons. These data
should provide additional
information about the nature of the mind
“body” in its out-of-body
state. More detailed evidence of veridical
NDE perceptions will
strengthen the case for the non-material
mind.
- NDE
physiological aftereffects:
When the mind has reunited with the brain
and body following NDE, there
generally are striking physiological
aftereffects (heightened
sensitivities, electrical effects, etc.),
which probably result from
the incomplete reintegration of the mind
with the physical body. A
direct study of unusual physiological
aftereffects, especially just
following NDE, should provide further
insight about the mind in
relation to the body.
- Other
neurological phenomena:
In principle, all neurological phenomena
should be explainable in terms
of the self-conscious mind interacting with
the brain. There are
particular phenomena that might provide
interesting insights and
confirmation of this theory, for example,
phenomena which might better
be explained by the principle of “coming to
awareness” such as the
cutaneous rabbit, blindsight and split brain
phenomena. Additionally,
the interface of the mind with neurons might
be unraveled through a
detailed study of the intercellular
structures of specific regions of
the cortex such as M1 and V1-V4.
Mind
is a
fundamental entity, a new dimension of
reality
The
self-conscious mind as conceived in
this theory does not fit other known physical
phenomena or known
physical laws.
It follows then that mind must be a
fundamental entity, a new dimension
of
reality, and the
domain of what constitutes “the physical” must
necessarily be
expanded to include minds. The
proposition that a non-material mind
interacts with electrical brain
processes
means that there must be some sort of force
which brings about the
interaction.
We expect that this force must ultimately
induce or translate into
electrical
effects in the neurons.
The
essential property of the mind is
the conscious experience of a particular
individual. The mind is the
seat of
the essential selfhood of the person; it is
the
person. Conscious
experience arises necessarily within the
mind’s field of phenomenal
experience,
through the direct interaction of the mind
with the person’s brain.
References
Bayne,
T., and
Chalmers, D. J. (2003). What is the unity of
consciousness? In A.
Cleeremans
(ed.), The Unity of
Consciousness: Binding,
integration and dissociation. Oxford, England: Oxford University
Press.
Blanke,
O., Ortigue,
S., Landis, T., and Seeck, M. (2002).
Stimulating illusory own-body
perceptions:
The part of the brain that can induce
out-of-body experiences has been
located. Nature, 419, 269-270.
Blanke,
O., Landis,
T., Spinelli, L., and Seeck, M. (2004).
Out-of-body experience and
autoscopy of
neurological origin. Brain,
127, 243-258.
Brodmann,
K.
(1909). Localisation in the
Cerebral
Cortex. Translated by L. J. Garey. New
York, NY:
Springer (2006).
Brugger,
P.,
Kollias, S. S., Müri, R. M., Crelier, G.,
Hepp-Reymond, M.-C., and
Regard, M.
(2000). Beyond re-membering: Phantom
sensations of congenitally absent
limbs. Proceedings of the National Academy
of
Sciences of the United
States of America, 97,
6167–6172.
Chalmers,
D.
J. (1996). The Conscious Mind:
In search
of a fundamental theory. New
York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Churchland,
P.
M. (1988). Matter and
Consciousness: A
contemporary introduction to the
philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Dennett,
D. C.
(1991). Consciousness Explained.
Boston:
Little Brown & Co.
Descartes,
R.
(1641). Meditations on First
Philosophy,
with selections from Objections and
Replies, J. Cottingham
(ed.). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press
(1996).
Greyson,
B.
(2000). Near-death experiences. In E.
Cardeña, S. J. Lynn and
S. Krippner (eds.), Varieties of
anomalous
experience: examining the
scientific evidence
(pp. 315-352). Washington, DC:
American Psychological Association.
Greyson,
B.,
Kelly, E. W., and Kelly, E. F. (2009).
Explanatory models for
near-death experiences. In J. M. Holden, B.
Greyson, and D. James
(eds.), The
Handbook of
Near-Death Experiences: Thirty years of
investigation.
Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger Publishers.
James,
W.
(1890). The principles of
psychology. New
York, NY:
Henry Holt.
Leskowitz,
Eric (2000). Phantom limb pain treated with
Therapeutic Touch: a case
report. Archives of Physical
Medicine and
Rehabilitation, 81, 522-524.
Leskowitz,
Eric (2001). Phantom limb pain: subtle
energy perspectives. Subtle
Energies and Energy Medicine, 8(2),
125-152.
Libet,
B.
(1973). Electrical stimulation of cortex in
human subjects, and
conscious
sensory aspects. In A. Iggo (ed.), Handbook
of sensory physiology, volume II:
Somatosensory system (pp.
743–790). Berlin, Germany:
Springer-Verlag.
Libet,
B. (1985).
Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role
of conscious will in
voluntary
action. Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 8,
529–566.
Libet,
B.
(1993). Neurophysiology of
consciousness:
Selected papers and new essays. Boston, MA:
Birkhäuser.
Libet,
B.
(2004). Mind time: the temporal factor
in consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Libet,
B.,
Alberts, W. W., Wright, E. W., Lewis, M.,
and Feinstein, B. (1975).
Cortical
representation of evoked potentials relative
to conscious sensory
responses,
and of somatosensory qualities – in man. In
H. H. Kornhuber (ed.), The
somatosensory system (pp. 291–308). Acton, MA:
Publishing Sciences Group.
Libet,
B.,
Gleason, C. A., Wright, E. W., and Pearl, D.
K. (1983). Time of
conscious intention to act in relation to
onset of cerebral activity
(readiness-potential): The unconscious
initiation of a freely voluntary
act. Brain, 106, 623–642.
Libet,
B.,
Pearl, D. K., Morledge, D. E., Gleason, C.
A., Hosobuchi, Y., and
Barbaro, N.
M. (1991). Control of the transition from
sensory detection to sensory
awareness in man by the duration of a
thalamic stimulus: The cerebral
“time-on”
factor. Brain, 114,
1731–1757.
Lutz,
A., and
Thompson, E. (2003). Neurophenomenology:
integrating subjective
experience and
brain dynamics in the neuroscience of
consciousness. Journal
of Consciousness Studies, 10, 31-52.
Mays,
R. G.,
and Mays, S. B. (2008a). The phenomenology
of the self-conscious mind. Journal
of Near-Death Studies, 27(1),
5-45.
Mays,
R. G.,
and Mays, S. B. (2008b). Phantom limb
“touch” suggests that a
“mind-limb”
extends beyond the physical body. Poster
presentation at Toward
a Science of Consciousness Conference,
April
8-12, 2008, Tucson, AZ.
Moody,
Jr., R.
A. (1975). Life after life: the
investigation of a phenomenon
– survival of
bodily death. New
York, NY:
Bantam Books.
Moody,
Jr., R.
A. and Perry, P. (1988). The light
beyond. New
York, NY:
Bantam Books.
Nikolajsen,
L., and Jensen, T. S. (2001). Phantom limb
pain. British
Journal of Anaesthesia, 87(1),
107-116.
Pascual-Leone,
A., Dang, N., Cohen, L. G., Brasil-Neto, J.
P., Cammarota, A., and
Hallett, M.
(1995). Modulation of muscle responses
evoked by transcranial magnetic
stimulation during the acquisition of new
fine motor skills. Journal of
Neurophysiology, 74, 1037–1045.
Penfield,
W.,
and Rasmussen, T. (1950). The
Cerebral
Cortex of Man: A clinical study of the
localization of function. New
York, NY:
Hafner Publishing Co.
(1968).
Popper,
K. R.,
and Eccles, J. C. (1977). The self and
its brain: an argument
for interactionism. London:
Routledge.
Ryle,
G.
(1949). The Concept of Mind.
New
York, NY: Hutchinson's
University Library.
Schwartz,
J.
M. (1999). A role for volition and attention
in the generation of new
brain
circuitry: Toward a neurobiology of mental
force. Journal
of Consciousness Studies, 6, 115–142.
Sheldrake,
R.
(1995). Seven Experiments that
Could
Change the World: A do-it-yourself guide
to revolutionary science. Rochester, VT: Park
Street
Press
(2002).
|